maandag 30 september 2013

Vitamin C Loss Is Not Evolution’s Gain


Evolution predicts gain of function; genetic entropy predicts loss of function.  A gene that helps synthesize Vitamin C provides a test between the two views.  Is there evidence for the origin of this gene?  Or does the mutation history show loss of function spreading by entropy over various lineages of mammals?  A recent pro-evolutionary paper cannot ignore the losses, but tries to give evolutionary explanations anyway.
Humans are among vertebrates that have lost the ability to synthesize Vitamin C and must obtain it from diet.  Other scurvy knaves include some bats, some birds, some fish, guinea pigs and anthropoid apes like chimpanzees.  In those cases, loss of function of one gene named GULO prevents the final step in Vitamin C (Vc) synthesis; otherwise, the GULO gene is highly conserved among mammals.  A team from the UK and China examined bats as a test case to determine what led to the loss, and published their results in PLoS ONE.

The authors state, “The ability to synthesize Vc has been reported in many ancestral vertebrate lineages, suggesting the ability for de novo synthesis is ancient.”  They did not indicate how Vc synthesis arose anywhere in the paper: nothing about gain of function or transitional forms, other than this one statement: “there is an apparent transition of the organs used for the biosynthesis of Vc during evolution, from the kidney of reptiles to the liver of mammals.”  However, loss of function is mentioned throughout.

Our recent research has challenged the traditional opinion that bats cannot synthesize Vc by showing that GULO genes in two species (Rousettus leschenaultii and Hipposideros armiger) are still in their intact forms and can produce functional proteins,” they said.  “Bats are perhaps in the process of large-scale loss of Vc biosynthesis ability, and show varying degrees of lack of GULO function.”  From this information, they traced the lineages of bats that have Vc synthesis and those that have lost it.  Assuming bats evolved from a common ancestor (which they did not specify as anything other than a fully-flying bat, but only inferred using phylogenetic software), they found a stepwise mutation pattern:

Interestingly, ancestral sequence reconstruction exhibits a stepwise mutation pattern (figure 4) that starts around the time when the tested bat species first evolved from a common ancestor around 58 mya. The ancestor of all bats maintains most of the original Laurasiatheria gene form (with only two mutations) after divergence with non-bat Laurasiatheria species; the ancestor of Hipposideridae, Rhinolophidae, and Megadermatidae (origin around 52 mya) has 3 mutations; the ancestor of Hipposideridae and Rhinolophidae (origin around 39 mya) has 4 mutations; the ancestor of Pteropodidae (origin around 23 mya) has 7 mutations; and the ancestor of the recently emerged Pteropus bats (around 3 mya) have 13 mutations, hence showing a stepwise accumulation of mutations during bat GULO evolution.


While this sequence is instructive (assuming their phylogenetic reconstructions are credible, based as they are on evolutionary dating), it does not show bats evolving into non-bats or gaining any new functions that were not already present in the putative common ancestor.  Instead, it shows mutations accumulating, and the bats losing an important function that, while not vital, would certainly be beneficial.


Ancestral reconstruction clearly shows a stepwise accumulating mutation pattern during bat GULO evolution. By mapping each mutation step with the origination times of each clade (figure 4), we surprisingly found that the more ancient the species are, the less mutations they had accumulated; conversely, more recently evolved bats often accumulated many mutations, which supports our hypothesis that Vc synthesis involving GULO is gradually becoming less important in bats. The ancestral bats were therefore presumably able to biosynthesize Vc, and during evolution, GULO gene function is gradually becoming redundant.


By redundant, they mean that if bats are able to ingest Vitamin C in their diets, the GULO gene is unnecessary.  Human sailors, of course, found that without citrus fruits on their ships, scurvy could be a fatal consequence.  Speaking of humans, there is evidence for a human GULO gene that has been mutated into a pseudogene: “The gene encoding GULO in guinea pigs and humans has become a pseudogene,” the authors said, referring to prior research.  If that gene could be restored, it might be possible to once again gain Vc synthesis function.  No more Vitamin C supplements!


In the mutant lineages of bats, too, once-active GULO pseudogenes were found.  “Bats showed lineage-specific gene pseudogenization including premature stop codons, insertions and deletions,” they said; in other lineages, the GULO genes were intact.  They inferred that purifying selection is acting to conserve the intact genes, but partial or complete loss is in progress: “We found that strong purifying selection has shaped non-Pteropus bat pseudogenes, suggesting these bats are in early stages of loss in their ability to synthesize Vc…. Thus we infer that pseudogenization of bat GULO evolved recently.


So while they spoke of evolution frequently, it is clear they were talking about degeneration of the bat genome through genetic entropy.  “In conclusion, our study shows that bats are beginning to lose their ability to biosynthesis vitamin C and some have lost this ability in no more than 3 mya. During gene degenerationstepwise mutation patterns are evident and these are important mechanisms leading eventually to pseudogenization.”


1. Cui J, Yuan X, Wang L, Jones G, Zhang S, 2011 Recent Loss of Vitamin C Biosynthesis Ability in Bats. PLoS ONE 6(11): e27114. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0027114.


Anyone see evolution here?  This is all downhill.  Abilities that once existed are being mutated away.  Where is the common ancestor of bats?  Only in software that assumes it existed, because Darwin’s theory demands that each animal “emerged” from something simpler.  Bats are notoriously resistant to this idea, because the oldest known fossil bat is 100% bat.  Dr. Duane Gish was arguing this for decades in his debates with evolutionists, and it is still true, despite plenty of time for fossil hunters to find a mouse with half-wings trying to attain batdom.
This paper is another example confirming Dr. John Sanford’s theory of genetic entropy (see Genetic Entropy and the Mystery of the Genome).  Mutations are dragging once-perfect genomes downward toward extinction. “Purifying selection” (not a creative process) weeds out the worst (usually by death), but allows many neutral or near-neutral mutations to accumulate, leading to weakened fitness.  Vitamin C synthesis is a good example, because diet can compensate for the loss of the GULO gene. Wouldn’t you really rather have it, though?
Bible believers may take interest in the idea of a genetic bottleneck at the time of the Flood.  The GULO gene was probably already mutating in the antediluvian world.  There were only 8 inhabitants on the Ark.  If they all had mutated GULO genes, then every human since would be deprived of Vitamin C synthesis.  Interesting, is it not, that that is just what we observe.

- See more at: http://crev.info/2011/11/111102-vitamin_c_loss/#sthash.MvBjbfI9.dpuf

How Birds Evolved by Incorrigible Storytelling
















An article by a free-lance science writer about dinosaurs evolving into birds takes the cake for speculative just-so storytelling, but it got published and republished anyway.


It’s not often that a whole article deserves “Stupid Evolution Quote of the Week,” but this one comes close: “How Birds Evolved From Small Meat Eating Dinosaurs,” by Joel N. Shurkin, published by Inside Science News Service and republished by Live Science.  Aside from beginning with the Kipling-style title, Shurkin wrote a completely fact-free story, relying on nothing but imagination: in short, “The arms got longer, the legs got shorter, and they were flying.


Shurkin assumes that for one reason or another, limb proportions changed in dinosaurs.  “Some time, perhaps 150 million years ago, small-feathered dinosaurs called maniraptorans began to develop longer arms and shorter hind legs, kick– starting the evolutionary process to becoming the birds we see today.”  They didn’t just start flying, “of course,” he quips as he launches into storybook land:

ISome of the creatures had longer wings and maybe shorter legs than others and found they could run faster and be more maneuverable than others. From there, natural selection took over.… 


I Their bodies got smaller, their forearms larger, the rear limbs shorter.

 What happened then? One possible — if simplistic — scenario is that one     day, one of the creatures with longer arms, while leaping over a hole, or snapping at something to eat, or trying to avoid being eatenspread its forearms, and left the ground for a second or two. He or she tried it again, maybe flapping the arms, and suddenly he or she was flying.

I Just like that.  The rest was just refinements. “This, of course, happened over millions of years.”  Of course.

Shurkin also had stories for how flying reptiles emerged, and flying mammals, too (bats).  They “probably evolved the same way,” he said, relying on his storytelling assistants, Hans Larsson of McGill University and Gregory Erickson of Florida State.  At least the storytellers them left themselves an out:


I“It’s hard to reconstruct the capacity for flight,” he said. To fully understand the process scientists would need to apply “forensic science to the fossil record” because scientists don’t have samples of the muscles. Larsson’s study, he said, was the best done so far, but it is still an educated guess.

I“We’ll never really know,” Erickson said.


The article on Inside Science set off a lively set of comments by a creationist reader.  To settle the issue, they all might best watch the documentary Flight: The Genius of Birds.  In the film, several scientists explore the “multiple independent points” that work together in a bird to allow powered flight in the heavier-than-air creatures: hollow bones, a redesigned respiratory system, movement of the center of mass, the most efficient digestive system in the animal kingdom, special flight musculature, navigation systems, orientation systems, flight feathers with a million parts each, and much more.



Unfettered storytelling is the besetting sin of evolutionists.  Coupled with an imagined omnipotent power of the Stuff Happens Law (natural selection), no story is too silly to get told, retold and admired by the Darwin Party.  Rescue a storyteller today; take them to Storytellers Anonymous or to a deprogramming session, where they must write “I will not tell just-so stories” on the board 100 times before lunch.  Especially hard cases might require devices that deliver a mild electric shock on the wrist every time they say “maybe” or “might have” or “scenario.”  There can be outdoor experiments, too.  Take the subject outside to run on a track with a hole in it, and instruct him to stretch out his forearms and flap as he jumps over the hole.  If he still thinks this could lead to human flight by natural selection (but over millions of years, “of course,”) ask which accidental mutations will get passed on to his offspring that have anything to do with his experience of jumping over a hole and flapping his forearms.  Deprogramming requires a lot of patience and time.  That’s why so few invest effort in it.  It explains evolutionary storytellers, like lost souls, roam the halls of academia, addicted to their habit, lacking a merciful hand to intervene.  There’s a quicker alternative: buy copies of Flight: The Genius of Birds to share with them.  Blessed are the merciful.

- See more at: http://crev.info/2013/09/how-birds-evolved-by-incorrigible-storytelling/#sthash.k5yCaF8T.dpuf
A Behavioral Problem
Evolutionary Psychology Explains . . . Itself?


by Denyse O'Leary

Have you ever wondered when a friend would finally grasp that her boyfriend is just bad news in trousers? If your “friend” were the human race, then evolutionary psychology (EP) is the boyfriend. And it looks as though she is finally beginning to get it. Evolutionary psychology? You must have heard: Evolution, not morality, explains why people return lost wallets (or don’t), run up charge card bills (or don’t), kill their children (or don’t), believe in God (or don’t), and do (or don’t) just about anything that currently interests the editor of the Relationships section of your weekend newspaper.
The basic idea is that, in the Old Stone Age, selfish genes blindly sought to replicate themselves. If those responsible for the neurons in our brains programmed behavior that caused a cave man to leave many descendants, the drive to procreate became part of our mental equipment. Essentially, little programs like these in our brains cause us to behave the way we do. So the reason we return the lost wallet is not because our minds have made a moral decision, but because our selfish genes have been programmed to do so.
Armed with this unproven concept, EP proponents can explain any behavior, or its opposite, by concocting a theory about how it helped our ancestors survive. That is easy to do because we have almost no information about Old Stone Age social life. Sometimes, cute psychological tests are devised to demonstrate a selfish gene’s program—with the results spilling into journalists’ inboxes as triumphant further evidence of EP. Journalists adore evolutionary psychology because it is a good story, and easy to tell.

Skeptical Mutterings

But winds change and fads peter out. Commentators have begun to mutter: The study of evolution is historical science, but evolutionary psychology may not be any type of science.
At first, the critiques focused on implausibility. In 1997, neuroscientist Vilayanur Ramachandran offered a parody, “Why Do Gentlemen Prefer Blondes?”, but was embarrassed when he was taken seriously. Ramachandran is a strict materialist who wanted to demarcate science from storytelling. Agnostic common-sense philosophers David Stove and Jerry Fodor have assailed EP’s simplistic and counterintuitive assertions about human nature. Social scientists such as Steven and Hilary Rose, editors of the anthology Alas, Poor Darwin, weighed in on its counterfactual assumptions about human behavior.
But a culture looking for blame-free explanations of bad or foolish behavior ignored these efforts. Anyway, they were drowned out by cries that the speculation was “based on the science of evolution,” which reveals with certainty what was better (adaptive) for our ancestors—even when the answers are contradictory. As Sharon Begley pointed out recently in Newsweek (June 29, 2009),
From its inception, evolutionary psychology had warned that behaviors that were evolutionarily advantageous 100,000 years ago (a sweet tooth, say) might be bad for survival today (causing obesity and thence infertility), so there was no point in measuring whether that trait makes people more evolutionarily fit today. Even if it doesn’t, evolutionary psychologists argue, the trait might have been adaptive long ago and therefore still be our genetic legacy. An unfortunate one, perhaps, but still our legacy. Short of a time machine, the hypothesis was impossible to disprove. Game, set and match to evo psych.
But not so fast. Absent a time machine, a hypothesis that supposedly explains everything may in fact explain nothing.

Reactive & Adaptive

The key problem with evolutionary psychology emerged from the Decade of the Brain project in the 1990s. The brain is not a series of linked modules; it is a restless sea in a semisolid state, constantly reordering itself, according to the focus of attention provided by the mind. Adapting to one’s environment is constant and normal. Echoes from the past are just that, dimly heard echoes, not prophecies of our behavior today.
In her Newsweek article, Begley talks about a new discipline in psychology, offering a much more accurate interpretation of human behavior: behavioral ecology. Behavioral ecology accepts evolution but does not assume that a given behavior is—or ever has been—always adaptive or otherwise. Predictions can be made only for specific ecologies.
For example, is it better for a girl to marry at puberty or to wait? To marry a rich old man or a strong young one? To marry a cousin or an outsider? Obviously, we need to know the circumstances of the society—the specific human ecology—to answer such questions. And the only thing encoded in the girl’s genes or neurons is a general human ability to react and adapt to her circumstances.
So what now for evolutionary psychology? Given the growing skepticism, based on knowledge of the brain’s workings, the affair is probably over. Unless the time machine is invented soon, EP will join social Darwinism and sociobiology in the museum of failed attempts to explain human behavior by appeals to the Old Stone Age. As to why we rape, kill, and sleep around? Sharon Begley insists that “the fault, dear Darwin, lies not in our ancestors, but in ourselves.”

- See more at: http://www.salvomag.com/new/articles/salvo11/11oleary.php#sthash.35AKF16R.dpuf
- See more at: http://www.salvomag.com/new/articles/salvo11/11oleary.php#sthash.35AKF16R.dpuf
STUMPED BY DESIGN


ID's Critics Engage in Motive-Mongering to Avoid the Evidence
By Casey Luskin


In August 2010, the creators of Salvo graciously invited me to speak at the University Club in downtown Chicago. After a short 40 minute presentation on the positive scientific case for intelligent design (ID), we opened up the floor to the audience.
Most of the inquiries led to serious and worthwhile scientific discussions. But one gentleman was confident he came armed with a "gotcha question" that would stump me. His challenge essentially boiled down to this: What about the 'Wedge Document'?
The Wedge What?
Salvo readers generally believe—quite rightly—that seeking truth requires merely following the evidence where it leads. As a result, they don't get bogged down in endless debates about personal motives or the religious (or non-religious) beliefs of scientists. At the end of the day, what matters is the evidence. Right?
For many ID critics, that's not right. In fact those who follow the ID debate closely are depressingly familiar with the fallacious distraction of the "wedge document."
While the "Wedge document" has no bearing on whether the information-rich molecular machines that underlie every living cell point to an intelligent designer, it's worth rebutting to help those who are seeking truth understand this debate
What is now called the "Wedge document" was originally a short fundraising packet compiled in the late 1990s by the pro-ID think tank Discovery Institute ("DI"). Like any good prospectus, it laid out the goals of the DI, centering around using pro-ID arguments to influence various branches of culture, including science, politics, education, and theology.
As the story goes, DI employed the services of a local copy store to duplicate the document. Some overzealous employees breached the store's duty to its clients by stealing a copy of the packet, which eventually led to it being leaked online.
When these events transpired, I was still taking G.E. courses in my undergraduate studies. But this much I can say for sure: Critics have been using the "Wedge document" ever since as a convenient excuse to dismiss ID without addressing its arguments.
"Go to Wikipedia"
"You can find it easily online," my self-assured challenger instructed me and the audience. "Go to Wikipedia and type in 'wedge document' and you can get copies of this thing. It says design theory promises to reverse the stifling dominance of the materialist worldview and to replace it with a science consonant with Christian and theistic convictions."
"There are other things," he continued.
"Governing goals of the wedge: to defeat scientific materialism and its destructive, moral, cultural and political legacies. To replace materialistic explanations with the theistic understanding that humans are created by God. 20 year goals. To see design theory as the dominant theory in science."
Having patiently waited a few minutes for the gentleman to finish (he eventually did ask a question), I was ready to respond.
Denying nothing in the Wedge document, I started by thanking him for reading a section often omitted by ID-critics—the part which describes the long-term goal for ID to become an established, respected field of science. If one reads the Wedge document carefully, I explained, it makes it clear that every goal outlined is to be driven by scientific research.
But this was not enough for my friend who assured me and the audience that the Wedge document showed the "origins of the [ID] movement are theological in nature."
When objections are brimming with logical fallacies, multiple levels of reply are often necessary.
The Genetic Fallacy
The first level of reply is that this question commits the genetic fallacy, which attacks the origin of an argument rather than the argument itself.
The ID movement is a collection of scientists and other scholars with a wide variety of beliefs and backgrounds. Many—though not all—are Christians. There are also Jews, Muslims, and individuals of other faiths. Some notorious ID proponents are not even religious.
But all of this is irrelevant to whether ID is correct. The personal religious (or non-religious) views or motives of people in the ID movement do not determine whether their scientific arguments hold merit.
For example, consider the great scientists Kepler and Newton. They were inspired by their religious convictions that God would create an orderly, rational universe with comprehensible physical laws. Their ideas turned out to be right—not because of their religious beliefs—but because the scientific evidence validated their hypotheses.
The Origins of Intelligent Design
The next stage of reply corrects historical errors made by the challenger. The origin of the ID movement was driven by science, not theology.
The first arguments for design in nature were made by ancient Greek philosophers—smart guys like Plato and Aristotle. They were not Christians—in fact they pre-dated Christianity by hundreds of years. Fast forwarding a couple thousand years, the term "intelligent design" was used by mainstream scientists as early as the 19th century, long before the advent of the creationist movements.
The scientific discoveries that inspired the modern ID movement commenced in the 1950s and 60s when biologists realized that life is fundamentally based upon a non-material entity, information. The visionary chemist Michael Polanyi explained this in a 1968 article in the journal Science titled, "Life's Irreducible Structure":
"Whatever may be the origin of a DNA configuration, it can function as a code only if its order is not due to the forces of potential energy. It must be as physically indeterminate as the sequence of words is on a printed page."
While Polanyi predated the modern ID movement and was not pro-ID, in the ensuing years a number of credible scientists became convinced that the information in life required an intelligent cause.
The term "intelligent design" appears to have been coined in its contemporary scientific usage by the atheist cosmologist Fred Hoyle. In his 1982 book Evolution from Space, he argued that "if one proceeds directly and straightforwardly in this matter, without being deflected by a fear of incurring the wrath of scientific opinion, one arrives at the conclusion that biomaterials with their amazing measure of order must be the outcome of intelligent design."
Another early pro-ID scientist was Charles Thaxton, a chemist who in 1984 published a highly influential book, The Mystery of Life's Origin, which argued that life's information pointed to design. Soon thereafter, Thaxton served as academic editor for the first pro-ID textbook Of Pandas and People. In 2005, "Pandas" gained notoriety by being at the center of a lawsuit that sought to ban ID from public school science classrooms in Dover, Pennsylvania.
"I wasn't comfortable with the typical vocabulary that for the most part creationists were using because it didn't express what I was trying to do," stated Thaxton in his deposition testimony for the Dover trial. "They were wanting to bring God into the discussion, and I was wanting to stay within the empirical domain and do what you can do legitimately there."
Thaxton was never called as a witness by the Dover plaintiffs—perhaps because his testimony made it clear that the origins of ID stemmed from a desire to pursue science. According to Thaxton, he preferred ID's approach because it differed from creationism and made a strictly scientific argument.
Guided by Thaxton's scientific methodology, Pandas explains that "If science is based upon experience, then science tells us the message encoded in DNA must have originated from an intelligent cause." However, this early ID work cautions that "if we go further, and conclude that the intelligence responsible for biological origins is outside the universe (supernatural) or within it, we do so without the help of science." According to Pandas, ID's scientific approach doesn't go that far, for "All it implies is that life had an intelligent source."
From its earliest days, ID thus sought to avoid getting into religious arguments about the identity or nature of the designer.
This continues to be ID's approach. In his book Signature in the Cell published in 2009, Stephen Meyer argues that, "Though the designing agent responsible for life may well have been an omnipotent deity, the theory of intelligent design does not claim to be able to determine that."
But Is It Science?
In a segment of my talk unrebutted by the critic, I explained that ID uses the scientific method to make its claims.
The scientific method is often described as a four-step process involving observation, hypothesis, experiment and conclusion.
Like any good scientific theory, ID starts with observations of the natural world. ID theorists observe human intelligence to understand the types of information and structures produced when intelligent agents act. These observations have been used to construct a cause-and-effect relationship between intelligence and the origin of certain types of information. ID theorists observe that intelligent agents are the sole known cause of high levels of complex and specified information, or "CSI" (see Salvo 13 for a discussion).
ID theorists then hypothesize that if a natural object was designed, it will contain high CSI. A variety of experiments can detect high CSI. Mutational sensitivity tests ask how finely-tuned an amino acid sequence must be in order to generate a functional enzyme. Genetic knockout experiments can be used to determine if a structure is irreducibly complex—a special type of CSI where a system requires all of its parts to function.
Such experiments have been conducted by ID proponents on biological systems to conclude that some of them bear the hallmarks of intelligent design.
ID critics are welcome to disagree with this argument. But harping upon the religious beliefs of ID proponents won't change the fact that ID's methodology is scientific.
What's Sauce for the Goose
It seems clear that ID is grounded in science. But has theology played any role in the development and advancement of the ID movement? The third level of rebuttal to the "Wedge document" answers that question.
The short answer is "Yes, but so what?" The longer answer is rhetorically devastating to ID-critics.
Ignoring ID's scientific methodology, many critics argue that ID is not science due to the religious motives, beliefs, and affiliations of its proponents. With the "Wedge document" in hand, they trot out various quotes (some in-context, some not) discussing religious views of ID proponents.
These attacks against ID are not just logically fallacious, they're also highly hypocritical.
After all, what's sauce for the goose is sauce for the gander. Leading proponents of evolution have expressed stridently anti-religious beliefs and motives for advocating evolution, and have close ties to atheist and secular humanist organizations. If critics want to harp upon the religious beliefs, motives, affiliations, and implications associated with ID, then they should realize that the argument cuts both ways.
Of course the most notorious example is Richard Dawkins, who holds the duel-honor of being the world's most famous evolutionist and its most famous atheist. Formerly Oxford University's Charles Simonyi Professor for the Public Understanding of Science, Dawkins argues that belief in God is a "delusion" and that "Darwin made it possible to become an intellectually fulfilled atheist." Dawkins has stated his personal goal is "to kill religion," and in a speech before the American Humanist Association, he asserted that "faith is one of the world's great evils, comparable to the smallpox virus but harder to eradicate."
America's great champion of evolution, the late Stephen Jay Gould, similarly announced that "[b]efore Darwin, we thought that a benevolent God had created us," but because of Darwin's ideas, "biology took away our status as paragons created in the image of God." Gould repeatedly discussed the "radical philosophical content of Darwin's message"—a materialist message which holds that "Matter is the ground of all existence; mind, spirit, and God as well, are just words that express the wondrous results of neuronal complexity."
Darwin's defenders sometimes claim that Gould and Dawkins are outliers in their views. If only that were so.
A 2007 editorial by the editors of the world's top scientific journal, Nature, stated that "the idea that human minds are the product of evolution" is an "unassailable fact," and thus concluded, "the idea that man was created in the image of God can surely be put aside."
That same year, a poll published in The Scientist by Cornell researchers William Provine and Greg Graffin found that 79% of evolutionary biologists surveyed were "pure naturalists" and strikingly, "[o]nly two out of 149 described themselves as full theists."
Provine and Graffin themselves squarely fit in the 'pure naturalist' category.
Provine has stated that "belief in modern evolution makes atheists of people" and asserts stark implications of Darwinian biology:
"Naturalistic evolution has clear consequences that Charles Darwin understood perfectly. 1) No gods worth having exist; 2) no life after death exists; 3) no ultimate foundation for ethics exists; 4) no ultimate meaning in life exists; and 5) human free will is nonexistent."
As for Graffin, this Cornell-trained evolutionary biologist is also a founder of the anti-Christian punk-rock band, Bad Religion.
But the materialist implications of neo-Darwinism are not just asserted by passionate university professors or rock stars. They are also found in textbooks.
The widely-touted theistic evolutionist biologist Kenneth Miller has written in five editions of his popular high school biology textbooks that evolution works "without either plan or purpose" and is "random and undirected." Two other versions of Miller's textbooks contain a striking discussion of the implications of Darwinism:
"Darwin knew that accepting his theory required believing in philosophical materialism, the conviction that matter is the stuff of all existence and that all mental and spiritual phenomena are its byproducts."
Likewise, my own college evolutionary biology textbook declared that "[b]y coupling undirected, purposeless variation to the blind, uncaring process of natural selection, Darwin made theological or spiritual explanations of the life processes superfluous."
Also noteworthy is the fact that top Darwin lobbyists have strong ties to secular humanist groups.
Eugenie Scott—called by Nature "the nation's most high-profile Darwinist"—is director of the leading pro-Darwin advocacy group, the National Center for Science Education (NCSE). But Dr. Scott is also a public signer of the Third Humanist Manifesto. This "wedge document" for atheism is an aggressive statement of the humanist agenda to create a world with "without supernaturalism" based upon the view that "[h]umans are . . . the result of unguided evolutionary change" and the universe is "self-existing."
Another leading pro-evolution activist, Barbara Forrest, believes that philosophical naturalism is "the only reasonable metaphysical conclusion." Dr. Forrest sits not just on the board of the NCSE, but also on the Board of Directors of the New Orleans Secular Humanist Association.
Given these affiliations and implications, it's no coincidence that leading evolutionists are closely wedded to materialism. Harvard paleontologist and author Richard Lewontin explains how materialism is a key assumption propping Darwinian thought:
"[W]e have a prior commitment . . . to materialism. It is not that the methods and institutions of science somehow compel us to accept a material explanation of the phenomenal world, but, on the contrary, that we are forced by our a priori adherence to material causes to . . . produce material explanations . . . [T]hat materialism is absolute, for we cannot allow a Divine Foot in the door."
Even the leading Darwinian philosopher of science (and atheist) Michael Ruse admits that "for many evolutionists, evolution has functioned . . . akin to being a secular religion" whose main doctrine is "a commitment to a kind of naturalism."
So What?
Neo-Darwinian evolution is surrounded by a cloud of leading proponents with anti-religious motives, beliefs, and affiliations, who have plainly declared that their theory can have anti-theistic implications.
And they have every right to do this.
None of the quotes or observations listed above disqualify evolution from being scientific. Neo-Darwinian evolution is a scientific theory, and it should be studied in laboratories and taught in public schools.
In fact, since neo-Darwinism is a bona fide scientific theory, this shows that the religious or anti-religious motives, beliefs, or affiliations of scientists do not disqualify their scientific views from holding scientific merit. And the fact that some draw larger metaphysical implications from evolution simply shows that there's a difference between the implications of a theory and the hard data supporting it.
And that's the whole point: In science, religious or anti-religious beliefs, motives, affiliations, and larger philosophical implications don't matter. Only the evidence matters.
Hypocritically, many ID-critics eagerly apply this logic to exonerate evolution, but they refuse to apply it fairly to ID.
What About Francis Collins?
After presenting a shortened version of this argument to my challenger friend, his rejoinder was reduced to pointing out that there are proponents of evolution who are religious, whereas ID is supposedly uniquely affiliated with religion. In this typical response, he dropped the names of theistic evolutionists like Francis Collins and Ken Miller.
Logically, his counter-rebuttal fails because ID uses the scientific method to make its claims and we're back to the genetic fallacy. But he was also simply wrong about ID and religion.
Since ID does not have religious premises, there are leading non-religious advocates of ID. The famous atheist Anthony Flew announced in 2004 that "the findings of more than fifty years of DNA research have provided materials for a new and enormously powerful argument to design."
Likewise, in 2009 University of Colorado professor Bradley Monton wrote a book subtitled "An Atheist Defends Intelligent Design." Later that same year, Monton defended ID alongside agnostic David Berlinski in a debate where a theist and an atheist attacked ID.
Just as some evolutionists are religious, there are leading ID proponents who are not religious.
A Consonant Conclusion
The critic noted in his question that the Wedge document aims to "reverse the stifling dominance of the materialist worldview and to replace it with a science consonant with Christian and theistic convictions."
Do those words condemn ID? Not if we're going to be fair. After all, for every Wedge document there's a Humanist Manifesto.
What is more, the word "consonant" doesn't mean "equivalent to," but rather means "in agreement with." Just as many materialists seek a science consonant with atheism, some theists seek a science consonant with their own worldview. The objection cuts both ways.
But most importantly, all this motive mongering is irrelevant; only the scientific data will decide who is right.
Pro-ID scientists should be able to stake out scientific positions without being judged on the basis of their private religious beliefs, motives, or affiliations. Moreover, their views should not be disqualified from being scientific if people interpret ID's scientific claims to have larger metaphysical implications. Unless, that is, evolutionists want their theory to be disqualified from being science.
They don't want that, and neither do I. The best solution for all is to stop talking about motives and start talking about the scientific evidence. But let the reader be forewarned: many ID-critics won't be willing to take this fair, truth-seeking approach.
Apparently some ID critics find it easier to live with hypocritical and logically fallacious arguments than to face the empirical data supporting intelligent design. •
- See more at: http://www.salvomag.com/new/articles/archives/science/luskin.php#sthash.QVA1crKO.dpuf

National Review, John Farrell's Predictable and Misleading Review of Darwin's Doubt




triloellipsesbite.png
We're beginning to see a formula, repetitive and predictable, among critical reviews of Darwin's Doubt.
First, critics refuse to engage the central arguments of the book. Readers will recall that in Darwin's Doubt Meyer shows that the abrupt appearance of the Cambrian animals in the Cambrian period contradicts the Darwinian expectation of a slow, gradual unfolding of animal life. Nevertheless, readers will also know that Meyer's main argument concerns the cause of the origin of the Cambrian animals, not their pattern of appearance in the fossil record. Specifically, Meyer argues that the genetic information (as well as the circuitry and epigenetic information) necessary to produce novel forms of animal life is best explained by intelligent design, rather than by various unguided evolutionary processes (like the mutation-selection mechanism).
DebatingDD.jpegSecond, rather than engaging the book's primary arguments, critics seek to sow seeds of doubt in the minds of readers about Meyer's trustworthiness, impeaching his scientific credibility and expertise. They try to do this largely by nitpicking over secondary issues in the book. For example, Nick Matzke claimed that Meyer made "basic errors." Donald Prothero asserted that Meyer, in failing to agree that the Cambrian explosion is merely "an artifact of preservation," "deliberately and dishonestly distorts" the evidence.
We have already responded to these charges, showing that what Matzke called "errors" were not, according to leading authorities, errors at all, and that what Prothero called "dishonesty" actually represented the consensus view among leading Cambrian paleontologists. Now, writing in the conservative outlet National Review, longtime ID-basher and Huffington Post-contributor John Farrell employs the same strategy. (For responses to some of Farrell's previous misrepresentations of ID, see hereherehere, and here.)
Predictably, Farrell fails to engage Meyer's central argument. Indeed, he blatantly misrepresents it. After repeating the false claim that Meyer exaggerates the brevity of the Cambrian explosion (previously refuted here), he claims that Meyer argues for the Cambrian explosion mainly on the basis of the suddenness of the explosion. (While the abrupt appearance of the Cambrian animals is one feature of the explosion that Meyer argues intelligent design can explain, it is by no means the main basis for the inference to design that Meyer draws.) He also claims that Meyer's argument for intelligent design is based upon his own "personal incredulity" about the creative power of mutation and selection. Indeed, Farrell presents Meyer's argument for intelligent design as a purely negative argument against evolution. Farrell misrepresents Meyer as follows:
What he [Meyer] does is reject two bedrock principles of modern evolutionary biology: the common ancestry of all living things, and natural selection as the driving force of the evolution of new species. If you reject these two notions of evolutionary biology, then by default you're left with only one alternative: the discrete interventions of an intelligent agent, a Designer, to explain the origin and diversification of life.
Yet anyone who knows Meyer's work knows that his argument does not constitute a purely negative argument from ignorance, as Farrell's use of the phrase "personal incredulity" also implies, but instead is a positive inference to the best explanation based upon our knowledge of cause and effect. Specifically, Meyer does not just show that the main evolutionary mechanisms lack "the causal power" to produce the new functional information (both genetic and epigenetic) necessary to produce the Cambrian animals. He also argues that we know of a cause capable of producing functional information, including both digital and hierarchically organized forms of information. That cause is intelligent activity or intelligent design. Thus, he argues that intelligent design constitutes the best explanation for the explosion of new functional information in the Cambrian period.
Instead of addressing, or even accurately representing, Meyer's main argument for intelligent design, Farrell devotes a significant portion of his review to criticizing the book for the alleged misuse of an ellipsis. You read that right. He takes issue with Meyer's punctuation! Of course, Farrell presents this as a serious matter. He claims that by grouping together two quotations from different parts of an article by paleontologist Charles Marshall (and by omitting another passage), Meyer gives the false impression that Marshall affirmed something called the artifact hypothesis -- the idea that the missing ancestors of the Cambrian animals were not preserved in the Precambrian fossil record because they were too small or soft, an idea Meyer shows to be untenable later in the book.
But Farrell (who holds a BA in English and has no training in the earth sciences) badly misread both Marshall and Meyer.
First, Meyer did not claim that Marshall supported the artifact hypothesis, only that he "summarized" it.
Second, Marshall himself repeatedly does affirm the artifact hypothesis in the article in question and he clearly does so in the passages that Meyer quotes.
Third, the specific passage that Farrell objects to Meyer's omitting, the one directly following the first quotation Meyer provides of Marshall discussing the artifact hypothesis, addresses another topic altogether (i.e., the duration of the Cambrian explosion, not the artifact hypothesis). Thus, it was entirely appropriate for Meyer to group (and omit) the passages that he did. And he did not misrepresent Marshall in so doing.
That's the basic gist of what Farrell got wrong. Here's more of the background to help interested readers determine who did, and did not, read and represent Marshall correctly.
In Chapter 3 of Darwin's Doubt, Stephen Meyer describes and critiques versions of the artifact hypothesis. To introduce his readers to the artifact hypothesis, Meyer quotes various scientists who attempt to explain away the absence of Precambrian ancestral fossils in the sedimentary record on the basis of the incomplete preservation of these putative ancestors. He cites such modern evolutionary scientists as Eric Davidson, Gregory Wray, Jeffrey Levinton, and Leo Shapiro who propound this argument in relatively recent papers. He also demonstrates that this argument is not new, quoting a textbook from 1894, and another from the 1940s, using the artifact hypothesis to explain away the abrupt fossil appearance of animals. Farrell doesn't protest any of these quotations or citations, nor should he -- the artifact hypothesis has been widely invoked by evolutionary scientists to explain away the Cambrian explosion. (I remember being taught about this idea in an upper division "Biodiversity" evolutionary biology course during my undergraduate studies at UC San Diego.)
Farrell does take issue with one particular source Meyer quotes to summarize the artifact hypothesis. That is the aforementioned Charles Marshall in a 2006 paper in Annual Reviews of Earth and Planetary Sciences, "Explaining the Cambrian 'Explosion' of Animals." (It's available free online here.) Meyer quotes Marshall as follows (pp. 57-58):
University of California, Berkeley paleontologist Charles R. Marshall summarizes these explanations:
[I]t is important to remember that we see the Cambrian "explosion" through the windows permitted by the fossil and geological records. So when talking about the Cambrian "explosion," we are typically referring to the appearance of large-body (can be seen by the naked eye) and preservable (and therefore largely skeletonized) forms. . . . If the stem lineages were both small and unskeletonized, then we would not expect to see them in the fossil record.
Farrell does not contest Meyer's general point that evolutionary scientists have invoked the artifact hypothesis to explain away the Cambrian explosion. Farrell only objects to Meyer's use of this particular quotation. He claims that Meyer misrepresents Marshall as affirming the artifact hypothesis when he does not. That's where his beef with Meyer's punctuation comes in. He claims that Meyer misused an ellipsis to omit a passage that places the quotations he includes from Marshall in a different context. He also objects that the two quotations that Meyer groups together separated by an ellipsis are separated by 15 pages in Marshall's original text. According to Farrell:
I went to Marshall's paper and discovered that this passage had been lifted out of context, with the final statement -- the part after Meyer's ellipsis -- tacked on from 15 pages later in the article, a section in which Marshall was commenting on a detailed diagram outlining the various factors scientists deem relevant to understanding the entire Cambrian explosion. The implication of the cut-and-paste quote in Meyer's account is that a leading paleontologist is, like his colleagues, trying to explain away a significant challenge to evolution: the lack of intermediate forms in the Precambrian period. But in fact, Marshall was not doing that.
Farrell calls Meyer's use of Marshall a "misleading quotation" and explains why he thinks Meyer represented the argument:
Here are the key missing words from Marshall's passage that would have appeared immediately before Meyer's ellipsis:
Finally, I place the word "explosion" in quotation marks because, while the Cambrian radiation occurred quickly compared with the time between the Cambrian and the present, it still extended over some 20 million years of the earliest Cambrian, or longer if you add in the last 30 million years of the Ediacaran and the entire 55 million year duration of the Cambrian.
The passage Meyer lifted has nothing to do with intermediate life forms -- missing or not -- in the Precambrian.
Mr. Farrell is correct that the sentences are separated by 15 pages. But he is incorrect that Meyer misrepresented Marshall's arguments or that his use of the ellipsis (and his decision not to quote the intervening passage Farrell cites) in any way distorted Marshall's position. Notice that the passage Meyer omitted, the one that Farrell cites directly above, discusses a different topic than do the other two quotations, namely the duration of the Cambrian explosion, not why the ancestral forms of the Cambrian animals are generally missing from the Precambrian record. (Marshall's view is that the Cambrian explosion lasted 20 million years, or much longer if the Ediacaran period is included.) Notice also that Marshall begins that passage with the enumerative word "Finally" followed by a comma, clearly signalling the introduction of another separate point. Farrell misses this obvious exegetical clue and, thus, fails to understand Meyer's perfectly defensible reason for omitting the passage in question.
Notice also that both of the passages from Marshall that Meyer cites are summarizing the same idea. In particular, both passages describe the idea that the apparent explosion of animal life in the Cambrian (Marshall puts the word "explosion" in scare quotes) reflects the fact that large and hard-skeletonized parts are more easily preserved in the fossil record, and thus in his view the Cambrian explosion may be an artifact of imperfect preservation. The first passage that Meyer cites (before the ellipsis) clearly makes this point, for there Marshall states:
So when talking about the Cambrian "explosion," we are typically referring to the appearance of large-body (can be seen by the naked eye) and preservable (and therefore largely skeletonized) forms. ...
And the second passage that Meyer cites (the one after the ellipsis), found in Table 1 of Marshall's paper, also clearly discusses this same topic for there Marshall states:
If the stem lineages were both small and unskeletonized, then we would not expect to see them in the fossil record.
Farrell charges that these passages from Marshall's paper that Meyer quoted "had been lifted out of context." But it is hard to see how that is the case when Marshall is expounding the same point in both quotations and the text that Farrell objects to Meyer omitting is making a different point.seco
In any case, Meyer doesn't even claim that Marshall endorses the artifact hypothesis. Marshall's article is a review essay, and all Meyer says is that Marshall is "summarizing" the artifact hypothesis so readers may understand it. And clearly Marshall is doing at least that.
Even so, Marshall's paper does more than "summarize" the artifact hypothesis. It also seems to affirm it, making Meyer's use of Marshall's paper for this purpose doubly defensible. Indeed, if one reads the intervening text (the "missing" 15 pages to which Farrell objects) Marshall is mainly discussing various causal possible explanations for the Cambrian explosion. (His article was, after all, a scientific review article published in an "Annual Reviews" journal.)
In that section of the paper, Marshall writes that the artifact hypothesis comes into play as an auxiliary hypothesis in support of three possible explanations for the Cambrian explosion: the "increased oxygen level" hypothesis, the slow "developmental" evolution of the Cambrian animals, and the "origin of predation." Combined with the molecular clock hypothesis, these explanations span 7 of the 15 pages between the two offending quotations of Marshall. But if you read Marshall's paper, and his Table 1 carefully, you learn that Marshall believes that many of the explanations of the Cambrian explosion he's proposing also require the artifact hypothesis as an auxiliary explanation to help explain why the ancestors to the Cambrian animals are missing in the Precambrian fossil record. Some specific quotes help show this.
Shortly into those intervening 15 pages, Marshall states, "it is likely that evolutionary lineages have their origins in rocks older than their first observed occurrences in the fossil record." As evidence of this, he argues that "attempts to use molecular clocks to estimate the time of origin of the animal phyla have led to much larger estimates of the incompleteness of the fossil record." (Meyer doesn't ignore this argument, and addresses and rebuts the molecular clock argument in detail in Chapter 5 of Darwin's Doubt.) On the next page, Marshall argues that the Cambrian animals' "unskeletonized forebears almost certainly had an Ediacaran, and perhaps more ancient, existence" and thus "the fossil record typically misses the early history of major clades." But why, according to Marshall, do the Cambrian animals "have their origins in rocks much older" than where they're "first observed"? It's because, as Meyer quotes Marshall later stating, "If the stem lineages were both small and unskeletonized, then we would not expect to see them in the fossil record." That's the artifact hypothesis, and far from Marshall critiquing or rejecting it, the artifact hypothesis is a thread that is woven throughout that entire section of Marshall's paper -- appearing at the beginning and end (which Meyer quotes), as well as various points in the middle.
As to Farrell's charge that Meyer misuses an "ellipsis," this too is contrived, because, though the two quotes are separated by fifteen pages, they occur in similar contexts and make the same point. Indeed, Farrell failed to mention that the first quotation from Marshall appears in the body of Marshall's article, while the second occurs in a caption to Marshall's Table 1, which summarizes the discussion of the preceding pages of Marshall's main text, including his discussion of "the artifact hypothesis." Thus, there was a simple, obvious reason why Meyer used the ellipsis: he was grouping two quotations together that made the same point in helpfully different ways. Moreover, given the context of Marshall's larger discussion and the way he used his Table 1 to summarize it, the quotation in the figure caption clearly amplified his earlier points. Indeed, the two statements about the artifact hypothesis roughly bookend his main discussion, and somewhat different focus in the intervening text, about possible causal explanations of the explosion animal life in the Cambrian. Why not group together such related, bookending passages?
It is worth pointing out as well that even if Meyer had misconstrued Marshall's position on the artifact hypothesis, it would have had no material bearing on the argument Meyer was making, which shows you how superficial Farrell's review is. In point of fact, many evolutionary scientists (I noted some others that Meyer cites earlier) have tried to explain away the Cambrian explosion by citing the artifact hypothesis. Meyer isn't wrong to rebut an argument that is commonly made. So what exactly is Farrell's point? Farrell wants readers to think that Meyer is ignoring a stronger argument that Marshall makes.
Thus, the larger context for Farrell's complaints is that he takes issue with Meyer's discussion of the artifact hypothesis in Chapter 3 in order to accuse Meyer of failing to acknowledge the alleged "steps" of evolution in the fossil record which make the "artifact hypothesis" unnecessary as an explanation for the Cambrian explosion. This is an odd charge to make against Meyer. Farrell shows no awareness that Meyer discusses this supposed early fossil record of animal evolution in great detail in Chapter 4 of Darwin's Doubt.
In complaining about Chapter 3 of Meyer's book, Farrell writes:
Consider again the alleged absence of transitional intermediate fossils connecting the Cambrian animals to simpler Precambrian forms. Meyer argues that Darwinian scientists have no explanation for this; indeed, just as Darwin once did, they've tried to dismiss this challenge by falling back on the convenient hypothesis that the fossil record was poorly preserved and/or had been insufficiently sampled.
He then accuses Meyer of ignoring the alleged fact that, in reality, the Cambrian explosion "included a particular series of steps," because there is a "radiation of animal forms that shows a great deal of continuous evolution over a 50 million-year Cambrian period." This, supposedly, makes the artifact hypothesis superfluous. According to Farrell, by critiquing the artifact hypothesis, Meyer has erected a straw man, and failed to acknowledge a much stronger argument from evolutionary scientists, that there is in fact a long, continuous record of animal evolution.
We already responded to the charge that the Cambrian explosion lasted many tens of millions of years, showing that leading authorities mark the Cambrian explosion as a roughly 10 million year period of rapid evolution. So where does Farrell get this idea of a "50 million-year Cambrian period" of evolution? Farrell cites Charles Marshall's paper, but Farrell apparently misunderstood what Marshall wrote.
Marshall actually wrote that the animal radiation "extended over some 20 million years of the earliest Cambrian, or longer if you add in the last 30 million years of the Ediacaran." That's not 50 million years of the "Cambrian period," since 30 million of those years are from the Ediacaran period. And the Ediacaran period, of course, is from the late Precambrian, just before the Cambrian. Why is this significant? Because, as I noted, Meyer devotes Chapter 4 in Darwin's Doubt, to discussing the supposed Precambrian fossil record of animal evolution, including many fossils from the Ediacaran period.
In that chapter, appropriately titled "The Not Missing Fossils," Meyer looks at numerous fossils and explains why they don't solve the problem of the Cambrian explosion. On the contrary, they lack morphological affinities to the Cambrian animals that would link them to the Cambrian animals as possible ancestors. Meyer cites multiple leading authorities who agree that the Ediacaran fossils simply don't represent the kind of organisms necessary to serve as evolutionary ancestors to the Cambrian animals.
Indeed, in a diagram that Farrell claims Meyer ignores, Marshall seems to endorse Meyer's position on this. Marshall recognizes that the Precambrian fossils from the Ediacaran period are plagued by "Phylogenetic uncertainty," reflecting the fact that few think the fossils known from the Ediacaran represent clear ancestors to the Cambrian animals. Marshall writes that "the phylogenetic status of many of the Ediacaran taxa is uncertain. These uncertainties make unraveling this time of prelude to the Cambrian 'explosion' difficult." Much later in the paper Marshall tepidly proposes that "Perhaps some of the Ediacarans are in fact the missing bilaterian stem groups," but he isn't sure.
But bear in mind the broader point at stake here: Farrell wants you to think Meyer misquoted Marshall in order to avoid dealing with Marshall's discussion of fossils that purportedly document animal evolution. But it's not at all the case that Meyer fails to recognize this sort of argument - in fact he devotes an entire chapter to rebutting it. This discussion happens, however, in Chapter 4, long after Meyer's quotation on Marshall on an entirely different topic.
Ironically, far from misquoting Marshall or taking what he writes out of context, Meyer could have quoted Marshall in support of his argument that a straightforward reading of the fossil record shows an explosive appearance of animals. Marshall also notes that:
Valentine and colleagues (1991), in the only quantitative treatment of the suddenness of the Cambrian 'explosion,' conclude that the suddenness of the adaptive radiation is real, even when the incompleteness of the fossil and rock records is taken into account.
Marshall's article certainly does not describe the Precambrian fossil record as documenting a "continuous evolution" of animal life. Indeed, on page 357 of the article, Marshall asks poignantly about why the anatomical characteristics thought to be associated with Precambrian "stem groups" are missing in the fossil record. "Where are they?" he asks.
If anything, we could accuse Farrell of taking Marshall "out of context," for failing to recognize that Marshall, at points, admits that the record shows an abrupt appearance of animals. But it's better to not play Farrell's games, and just let the evidence speak for itself.
To recap what we have seen:
  • Meyer only said Marshall was "summarizing" the artifact hypothesis, and never claimed that Marshall endorsed it.
  • Marshall not only summarized the artifact hypothesis, but in fact endorsed it -- not just in the places Meyer quoted him, but also in the intervening pages represented by the offending ellipsis.
  • Meyer hardly ignores the other arguments Marshall makes in those intervening pages about a supposed Precambrian animal fossil record or a molecular clock, and in fact discusses them extensively in Darwin's Doubt. Farrell doesn't recognize any of this, but Chapter 4 of the book is devoted to assessing the alleged Precambrian animal fossil record, and Chapter 5 critiques the molecular clock.
  • Marshall even notes that a literal reading of the fossil record shows the abrupt appearance of animals, and he is skeptical that the Ediacaran fossils are the missing animal ancestors to the Cambrian animals. This is why the artifact hypothesis is woven as a theme and thread throughout his paper.
On top of all of this, Farrell frames Meyer's argument as a strictly negative critique of evolution based upon "personal incredulity," ignoring (and thereby failing to address) Meyer's extensive critique of the mutation-selection mechanism, as well as Meyer's rigorous positive case for design. Instead, Farrell takes the low road, refusing to engage Meyer's central arguments, and misrepresenting the literature, all for the purpose of impugning Meyer's scholarly integrity through a tired, worn-out -- and entirely baseless -- "out of context" quotation charge. This weak and contrived review is unworthy of a respected outlet like National Review.


http://www.evolutionnews.org/2013/09/in_national_rev076261.html#sthash.9b0n9iFg.dpuf